Results for 'John R. Blad'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  2
    Abolitionisme als strafrechtstheorie: theoretische beschouwingen over het abolitionisme van L.H.C. Hulsman.John R. Blad - 1996 - [Arnhem]: Gouda Quint.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization.John R. Searle (ed.) - 2009 - , US: Oxford University Press.
    The purpose of this book -- Intentionality -- Collective intentionality and the assignment of function -- Language as biological and social -- The general theory of institutions and institutional facts: -- Language and social reality -- Free will, rationality, and institutional facts -- Power : deontic, background, political, and other -- Human rights -- Concluding remarks : the ontological foundations of the social sciences.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   274 citations  
  3. Mind: A Brief Introduction.John R. Searle - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    "The philosophy of mind is unique among contemporary philosophical subjects," writes John Searle, "in that all of the most famous and influential theories are false." In Mind, Searle dismantles these famous and influential theories as he presents a vividly written, comprehensive introduction to the mind. Here readers will find one of the world's most eminent thinkers shedding light on the central concern of modern philosophy. Searle begins with a look at the twelve problems of philosophy of mind--which he calls (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  4. Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery.John R. Anderson - 1978 - Psychological Review (4):249-277.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   417 citations  
  5. Consciousness, explanatory inversion and cognitive science.John R. Searle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):585-642.
    Cognitive science typically postulates unconscious mental phenomena, computational or otherwise, to explain cognitive capacities. The mental phenomena in question are supposed to be inaccessible in principle to consciousness. I try to show that this is a mistake, because all unconscious intentionality must be accessible in principle to consciousness; we have no notion of intrinsic intentionality except in terms of its accessibility to consciousness. I call this claim the The argument for it proceeds in six steps. The essential point is that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   288 citations  
  6. Proper names.John R. Searle - 1958 - Mind 67 (266):166-173.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  7. How to derive "ought" from "is".John R. Searle - 1964 - Philosophical Review 73 (1):43-58.
  8. Is the Brain’s Mind a Computer Program?John R. Searle - 1990 - Scientific American 262 (1):26-31.
  9. Is the brain a digital computer?John R. Searle - 1990 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 64 (3):21-37.
    There are different ways to present a Presidential Address to the APA; the one I have chosen is simply to report on work that I am doing right now, on work in progress. I am going to present some of my further explorations into the computational model of the mind.\**.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  10. Consciousness.John R. Searle - 2000 - Intellectica 31:85-110.
  11. The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse.John R. Searle - 1975 - New Literary History 6 (2):319--32.
  12. What is an intentional state?John R. Searle - 1979 - Mind 88 (January):74-92.
  13. Indeterminacy, empiricism, and the first person.John R. Searle - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (March):123-146.
  14. What is an Institution?John R. Searle - unknown
    When I was an undergraduate in Oxford, we were taught economics almost as though it were a natural science. The subject matter of economics might be different from physics, but only in the way that the subject matter of chemistry or biology is different from physics. The actual results were presented to us as if they were scientific theories. So when we learned that savings equals investment, it was taught in the same tone of voice as one teaches that force (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  15. The intentionality of intention and action.John R. Searle - 1979 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 22 (1-4):253 – 280.
    This article presents a sketch of a theory of action. It does so by locating the relation of intention to action -vithin a general theory of Intentionality. It introduces a distinction between ptiorintentions and intentions in actions; the concept of the experience of acting; and the thesis that both prior intentions and intentions in action are causally self-referential. Each of these is independently motivated, but together they allow suggested solutions to several outstanding problems within action theory (deviant causal chains, the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  16. Austin on locutionary and illocutionary acts.John R. Searle - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (4):405-424.
  17. Minds and brains without programs.John R. Searle - 1987 - In Colin Blakemore & Susan Greenfield (eds.), Mindwaves: Thoughts on Intelligence, Identity, and Consciousness. Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  18. How performatives work.John R. Searle - 1989 - Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (5):535 - 558.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  19. Intentionalistic explanations in the social sciences.John R. Searle - 1991 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 21 (3):332-344.
    The dispute between the empiricist and interpretivist conceptions of the social sciences is properly conceived not as a matter of reduction or covering laws. Features specific to the social sciences include the following. Explanations of human behavior make reference to intentional causation; social phenomena are permeated with mental components and are self-referential; social science explanations have not been as successful as those in natural science because of their concern with intentional causation, because their explanations must be identical with the propositional (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  20. Fiduciary Duties and the Shareholder-Management Relation.John R. Boatright - 1994 - Business Ethics Quarterly 4 (4):393-407.
    The claim that managers have a fiduciary duty to shareholders to run the corporation in their interests is generally supported by two arguments: that shareholders are owners of a corporation and that they have a contract or agency relation with management. The latter argument is used by Kenneth E. Goodpaster, who rejects a multi-fiduciary, stakeholder approach on the grounds that the shareholder-management relation is “ethically different” because of its fiduciary character. Both of these arguments provide an inadequate basis for the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  21. Consciousness, free action and the brain.John R. Searle - 2000 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 7 (10):3-22.
    Commentary on John Searle's Article John Searle presents a philosopher's view of how conscious experience and free action relate to brain function. That view demands an examination by a neuroscientist who has experimentally investigated this issue.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  22. Consciousness, unconsciousness and intentionality.John R. Searle - 1991 - Philosophical Issues 1:45-66.
  23. Free will as a problem in neurobiology.John R. Searle - 2001 - Philosophy 76 (298):491-514.
    The problem of free will arises because of the conflict between two inconsistent impulses, the experience of freedom and the conviction of determinism. Perhaps we can resolve these by examining neurobiological correlates of the experience of freedom. If free will is not to be an illusion, it must have a corresponding neurobiological reality. An explanation of this issue leads us to an account of rationality and the self, as well as how consciousness can move bodies at all. I explore two (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  24. The problem of consciousness.John R. Searle - 1993 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 60 (1):3-16.
    The most important scientific discovery of the present era will come when someone -- or some group -- discovers the answer to the following question: How exactly do neurobiological processes in the brain cause consciousness? This is the most important question facing us in the biological sciences, yet it is frequently evaded, and frequently misunderstood when not evaded. In order to clear the way for an understanding of this problem. I am going to begin to answer four questions: 1. What (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  25. Language and social ontology.John R. Searle - 2009 - In Chrysostomos Mantzavinos (ed.), Philosophy of the social sciences: philosophical theory and scientific practice. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 443-459.
  26. Biological naturalism.John R. Searle - 2004
    “Biological Naturalism” is a name I have given to an approach to what is traditionally called the mind-body problem. The way I arrived at it is typical of the way I work: try to forget about the philosophical history of a problem and remind yourself of what you know for a fact. Any philosophical theory has to be consistent with the facts. Of course, something we think is a fact may turn out not to be, but we have to start (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  27. Response: Perception and the satisfactions of intentionality.John R. Searle - 1991 - In John Searle and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell.
  28. Chomsky's Revolution in Linguistics.John R. Searle - unknown
    Throughout the history of the study of man there has been a fundamental opposition between those who believe that progress is to be made by a rigorous observation of man's actual behavior and those who believe that such observations are interesting only in so far as they reveal to us hidden and possibly fairly mysterious underlying laws that only partially and in distorted form reveal themselves to us in behavior. Freud, for example, is in the latter class, most of American (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  29. Limits of phenomenology.John R. Searle - 2000 - In Mark A. Wrathall & Jeff Malpas (eds.), Heidegger, Coping, and Cognitive Science. MIT Press.
  30.  9
    The London evening courses of Benjamin Martin and James Ferguson, eighteenth-century lecturers on experimental philosophy.John R. Millburn - 1983 - Annals of Science 40 (5):437-455.
    A study of some London newspapers of the early 1770s has shown that Martin and Ferguson gave continuous courses of evening lectures during the winter, in direct competition with each other. In this paper the coverage of their courses is derived from their advertisements, and related to their publications and other activities. In some subjects, such as Electricity, Hydrostatics, and Air-pump Experiments, there was close correspondence between the courses, but others reflected the lecturers' primary interests: for Martin, Optics, and for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  31.  71
    Beyond the Sublime: The Aesthetics of the Analogy of Being (Part One).John R. Betz - 2005 - Modern Theology 21 (3):367-411.
    This essay is concerned with modern and postmodern theories of the sublime and with a possible theological response to them. The essay first discusses the “modern sublime” and the “postmodern sublime” , and shows how these versions of the sublime terminate in one or the other form of “pure immanence” and, hence, are not sublime in any standard sense of the term. The essay then argues, in a second part, for an aesthetic of the beautiful and the sublime based upon (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32. The Failures of Computationalism.John R. Searle - 2001 - Http.
    Harnad and I agree that the Chinese Room Argument deals a knockout blow to Strong AI, but beyond that point we do not agree on much at all. So let's begin by pondering the implications of the Chinese Room. The Chinese Room shows that a system, me for example, could pass the Turing Test for understanding Chinese, for example, and could implement any program you like and still not understand a word of Chinese. Now, why? What does the genuine Chinese (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33.  92
    Sortal predicates and quantification.John R. Wallace - 1965 - Journal of Philosophy 62 (1):8-13.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  34.  59
    The Explanation of Cognition.John R. Searle - 1997 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 42:103-.
    What sorts of systematic explanations should we and can we seek in cognitive science for perception, language comprehension, rational action and other forms of cognition? In broad outline I think the answer is reasonably clear: We are looking for causal explanations, and our subject matter is certain functions of a biological organ, the human and animal brain.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35. Real-Life Decisions and Decision Theory.John R. Welch - 2012 - In Sabine Roeser (ed.), Handbook of Risk Theory: Epistemology, Decision Theory, Ethics, and Social Implications of Risk. Springer Science & Business Media.
    Some decisions result in cognitive consequences such as information gained and information lost. The focus of this study, however, is decisions with consequences that are partly or completely noncognitive. These decisions are typically referred to as ‘real-life decisions’. According to a common complaint, the challenges of real-life decision making cannot be met by decision theory. This complaint has at least two principal motives. One is the maximizing objection that to require agents to determine the optimal act under real-world constraints is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36. The connection principle and the ontology of the unconscious: A reply to Fodor and Lepore.John R. Searle - 1994 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (4):847-55.
  37.  51
    A complete theory of natural, rational, and real numbers.John R. Myhill - 1950 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 15 (3):185-196.
  38.  20
    Enlightenment Revisited: Hamann as the First and Best Critic of Kant's Philosophy.John R. Betz - 2004 - Modern Theology 20 (2):291-301.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. The direct contextual realism theory of perception.John R. Shook - 2003 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 17 (4):245-258.
  40.  32
    Unesco's proposed declaration on bioethics and human rights – a bland compromise1.John R. Williams - 2005 - Developing World Bioethics 5 (3):210-215.
    ABSTRACTThe latest draft of UNESCO's proposed Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights is a major disappointment. The committee of government ‘experts’ that produced it made sure that it would not introduce any new obligations for States, and so the document simply restates existing agreements and lists desirable goals without specifying how they can be achieved. This article focuses on the shortcomings of the document as it would apply to health care. These shortcomings are evident in the document's scope, aims (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  26
    Methods in psychology; a critical case study of Pavlov.John R. Wettersten - 1974 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 4 (1):17-34.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  5
    Why Buber Would Not Endorse a Pseudo‐Existentialist.John R. Scudder - 1975 - Educational Theory 25 (2):197-201.
  43.  26
    Die metaphysische Bedeutung des Höchsten Gutes als Kanon der reinen Vernunft in Kants Philosophie.John R. Silber - 1969 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 23 (4):538 - 549.
  44.  35
    Brain and mind.John R. Smythies - 1965 - New York,: Humanities Press. Edited by Hartwig Kuhlenbeck.
  45.  9
    Eucharistic Reconciliation.John R. Berkman - 2004 - Journal for Peace and Justice Studies 14 (2):179-196.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  5
    Purkyněs Weg: Wissenschaft, Bildung und NationErna Lesky.John R. Berg - 1972 - Isis 63 (4):589-590.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. After Barth : a new introduction to Erich Pryzywara's Analogia Entis.John R. Betz - 2011 - In Thomas Joseph White (ed.), The Analogy of being: invention of the Antichrist or the wisdom of God? Cambridge, U.K.: W.B. Eerdmans Pub. Co..
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  16
    Postmodernity's Transcending: Devaluing God – By Laurence Paul Hemming.John R. Betz - 2007 - Modern Theology 23 (3):488-492.
  49.  70
    Transcendence without reality.John R. Wright - 2005 - Philosophy 80 (3):361-384.
    Thomas Nagel has held that transcendence requires attaining a point of view stripped of features unique to our perspective. The aim of transcendence on this view is to get at reality as it is, independent of our contributions to it. I show this notion of transcendence to be incoherent, yet defend a contrasting notion of transcendence. As conceived here, transcendence does not require striving for an external, objective viewpoint on nature or looking at matters from someone else's or an impartial (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  23
    Max Weber's methodological strategy and comparative lifeworld phenomenology.John R. Hall - 1979 - Human Studies 4 (1):131 - 143.
1 — 50 / 1000